|
||||
by Roger Koppl, Fairleigh Dickinson University I. Introduction. Alfred Schutz and F.A. Hayek developed two seemingly different systems of social thought. The two systems, however, are consistent and complementary. It is worthwhile to integration their theories. Doing so is likely to help us to solve some unresolved problems in several areas of economics and finance. The most important of these problems concern expectations. It may seem paradoxical or perverse to suggest integrating Schutz and Hayek. Alfred Schutz was a phenomenological sociologist. He was therefore a follower of the rationalist philosopher, Edmund Husserl. Like Husserl, Schutz emphasized subjective processes of meaning formation and interpretation. Hayek was an economist who adopted the very naturalism Husserl criticized as an absurdity (Husserl 1911, p. 81).[1] Hayek (1952b) was even guilty of what Husserl called the naturalizing of consciousness (1911, p. 80). Hayek was an anti-Cartesian who identified himself with the Scottish Enlightenment (1978 and 1994, p. 140). As a phenomenologist, Schutz formed part of a rationalist, continental tradition that was highly Cartesian in important respects. (One of Husserls last works was entitled Cartesian Meditations.) Schutz and Hayek might seem to inhabit quite different intellectual worlds. But both were followers of the economist Ludwig von Mises. Alfred Schutz and F.A. Hayek were Misesian economists. Each of them wrote important books defending the basic methodological position Mises articulated (Schutz 1932a, Hayek 1952a, 1952b). While each of them developed a methodological position that descends directly from Mises, they developed Mises ideas in very different ways. In this paper I will concentrate on their methodological views.[2] The interpretation of meanings was essential element in Mises methodology. Mises account of such understanding was based on Henris Bergsons idea of intuition. Both Schutz and Hayek replaced this account with another. Schutz replaced Bergsonian intuition with Husserls phenomenological psychology. Hayek replaced Bergsonian intuition with the meta-conscious recognition of patterns that are too complex for the conscious mind. I will argue that phenomenological psychology is perfectly consistent with Hayeks combinatorial account of understanding. If we recognize the Misesian character of each thinkers system, we can see how to integrate them into a larger, unified system. This larger system may facilitate progress on concrete problems in economics and finance. (I will give some examples later.) The differences in their ideas in philosophy and psychology turn out to pose no fundamental difficulty to the integration I propose. II. The Methodology of Ludwig von Mises A. The Elements of Mises System Between the wars Ludwig von Mises was the leader of the Austrian school of economics (Prendergast, 1986, p. 6). Mises saw himself as the heir to the schools founder, Carl Menger (Lachmann 1981, pp. vi-vii). Menger's Aristotelian methodological position had been articulated in the course of the famous methodenstreit conducted with the German Historical School (Prendergast, 1986, p.10). Mises felt that Mengers position needed to be rehabilitated as a part of the struggle against historicism, empiricism, and irrationalism (Mises, 1933, p. xxiv. See also Lachmann, 1981, p.v). Mises worked out his position in a series of articles, which were collected together in 1933 under the title Grundprobleme der Nationalökonomie (Epistemological Problems of Economics). The principle target of his critical attacks was the historicism of the German Historical School. But his arguments apply to many targets, including positivism. In his preface to the English translation of 1960, Mises leads with an attack on unified science, positivism, and scientism. From that introduction, one would imagine the book to have been targeted at the logical positivists of the Vienna Circle. It seems Mises considered his arguments equally effective against both groups. Lachmanns introduction notes that Mises may have given too much attention to the German historians and too little to logical positivism (p. vii). But he also notes that at precisely this time Vienna had become the headquarters of logical positivism and Mises book was a challenge to positivists and empiricists of almost every school (p. vii). Hayek was latter to argue for an essential connection between historicism and positivism (1952a). In Theory and History, Mises includes a chapter (The Challenge of Scientism) that explicitly attacks Otto Neurath, positivism, and behaviorism (Mises 1957, pp. 240-263.) Prendergast reports that the Austrian schools methodology had been severely weakened by the cumulative attacks of historicism, the Lausanne school of mathematical economics, and after 1928, logical empiricism (1986, p. 8). It seems fair, then, to describe Mises position as standing in opposition to both historicism and positivism. On the one side there was the German Historical School, i.e., the historicists. Among them, Max Weber had emerged as a towering figure, one whom Mises admired greatly and claimed as a friend. Weber explained that "interpretive sociology" uses "ideal types" to understand events. Weber's ideal-type methodology requires the analyst to refer to the "meaning" an action has to the actor. This is a thoroughgoing subjectivism. Weber's ideal-type method was arguably the leading form of subjectivism at the time Mises was working out his own position. In Weber's hands, unfortunately, it was the method of history. What we call "social science" was not science at all, but history. Though "wissenschaft," it was not nomological. For Weber and other members of the German historical school, the interpretation of meanings, verstehen, was historical and not scientific. It was historical because the meaning of an act is specific to time and place. It required a special intuition to grasp meanings, an intuition that apprehends the particulars of the situation. Science, by contrast, uses no such intuition; it does not employ verstehen. Science seeks general truths, not the particular truths reached by intuition. The historicists offered subjectivism without science. On the other side were the "logical empiricists," i.e., the positivists. The positivists of the Vienna Circle accepted the usual distinction between a priori, and a posteriori. They characterized the difference in their own way. Propositions a priori are true solely on account of the rules of grammar. An a posteriori proposition was meaningful only if it could be "verified." The meaning is the test and the test is a possible verification. The positivists insisted that "science" be "empirical" and their extreme brand of empiricism was verificationism. Attempted verifications of a proposition were to be "objective" procedures, fully explicit and public. No element of intuition was allowed to corrupt them. Meanings, according to the positivists, could not be observed nor, therefore, verified. The positivists offered science without subjectivism. To rehabilitate Menger's program, Mises needed to find a way out of both historicism and positivism. He had accepted, however, the historicists' argument that our intuitive understanding of meaning is particular and historical, not general. And he accepted the positivists claim that our a priori knowledge conveys no particulars about the world in which we live. His solution lay in the distinction between "conception" and "understanding." Mises identified "conception" and "understanding" as "two epistemologically distinct procedures." Conception is ratiocination, the sort of thing prized by the positivists. Understanding is intuition, the faculty prized by the historicists. In fact, for Mises understanding is Bergsonian intuition.[3] Mises' innovation, was to argue that we have an a priori "conception" of human action which enables us to "understand" particular acts. Conception gives the interpretive framework; understanding gives the interpretation. Conception gives us the form of action, understanding the substance. This is Mises' famous apriorism. The form of action is revealed by the a priori logic of praxeology. This is the scientific part of economics. The substance of action is revealed by the a posteriori insights of understanding. From conception we get theory; from understanding we get history. In this way, Mises was able to keep both science and understanding as essential elements of political economy. Mises position had five features important to us here. First, as we have seen, Mises argued for the existence of an a priori science of human action. Second,
Mises defended methodological
dualism. The method of
understanding is distinct from anything employed in the physical sciences.
Moreover, the pure a priori discipline of economic employs categories such as
preference exchange and purpose, which have no application in
physical science. Mises carefully distinguished methodological and metaphysical
dualism. Methodological
dualism, Mises explained, refrains from any proposition concerning
essences and metaphysical constructs.
It
simply accepts a basic fact, namely, that we do not know how external events
physical, chemical and physiological affect human thought and action.
It is an argument from ignorance. Our
ignorance splits the realm of knowledge into two separate fields, the realm
of . . . nature, and the realm of
human thought and action (Mises 1957, p. 1).
[4] Third,
Mises advocated the method of understanding or verstehen. As we
have seen, he thought Henri Bergson had properly properly characterized the
nature of understanding. He
also thought that the understanding he advocated was essentially that of
the historians, including Max Weber and other members of the German Historical
School. Mises credits members of
the German Historical School, including Max Weber, with providing the
clarification of the logical problems of the historical sciences. Although they did not realize that a universally valid
science of human action existed, this fact does not vitiate what they
accomplished for the logic of the historical sciences.
In particular, they brought into relief the distinctive logical
character of the historical sciences in connection with the doctrine of
`understanding (Mises 1933, p. xviii).[5] Mises fully accepted Webers method of ideal type for
history. Fourth,
Mises defended methodological individualism.
In Mises hands the concept meant simply that explanation of social
causation should not bypass the individual acts through which that causality
works. Collective entities
exist and operate. But they operate
through the agency of individual actors and individual actions. A collective whole is a particular aspect of the actions
of various individuals and as such a real thing determining the course of
events (1966, p. 43). I use the
term methodological individualism with some misgivings.
It has come to hurt, not help communication. Methodological individualism
is easily confused with ontological individualism, the doctrine that individuals
are prior to society and have the properties they do independently
of society. It is not clear what
such a claim might really mean. In any event, methodological individualism and ontological
individualism are not the same. Moreover,
methodological individualism is often taken to mean naive
methodological individualism. Neither
Mises, nor Schutz, nor Hayek argued for ontological individualism.
All three held to sophisticated versions of methodological individualism
that recognized societys role in shaping the individual.[6]
(Langlois 1989 contains a good review of the issues.)
Fifth,
Mises defended nomological theory. He
defended the existence of universally valid economic theory (1933, p. xxiv).
This theory provided laws that are analogous to the laws of physics.
Economics too can make predictions, Mises explains, in the sense
in which this ability is attributed to the natural sciences (1933, p. 118).
One must study the laws of human action and social cooperation as the
physicist studies the laws of nature (1966, p. 2).
Examples include what effect an increase in the quantity of money will
have on its purchasing power . . . what consequences price controls must
have, (1933, p. 118) and the future effects of a proposed change in
currency legislation (1933, p. xx). Note
that these are all examples of prediction within the realm of catallactics,
that is, the theory of markets (Mises, 1967, p. 232). Mises
system has, I think, been under-rated among economic methodologists.
(Caldwell, 1984 is an exception.) As
we shall see below, Schutz and Hayek both adopted fundamentally Misesian
methodological positions. Each of
these thinkers is recognized as a serious and important methodologist.
Mises student Fritz Machlup (1978) followed Mises and Schutz, and is
recognized as a leading methodologist. (The
widespread view that Machlup was a positivist is criticized in Langlois and
Koppl 1991.) Thus, we should
acknowledge Mises methodology as an important scholarly acheivement. Mises
system, however, has difficulties. It
probably cannot be sustained without the sorts of modifications proposed by
Schutz and Hayek. There are at least four difficulties with Mises' position.
First, and most importantly, it relies on Bergson's rather mysterious
notion of intuition (Mises 1933, pp. 130-145; 1967, pp 47-51, 881-882).
In Bergson's philosophy, intuition is the intellectual faculty which
allows one to "enter into" another object and "participate"
in its "motion." The knowledge thus acquired is supposed to be a kind
of completed infinity in which a "whole" is grasped (Mises 1933, p.
133-134; 1967, p.49; Bergson 1903, pp. 159-162). It seems doubtful that such a grasping of completed
infinities is really possible. Indeed,
I doubt the idea has a clear meaning. At
the same time it divides our acts of apprehension into two separate watertight
compartments. In the compartment
labeled "conception," everything is rational, analytical, and orderly.
In the compartment labeled "understanding," we transcend reason
and reach into the heart of things, discovering thereby such things as "the
quality of values" (Mises 1933, p. 133).
Such a sharp division probably does not exist in fact. Second,
Mises solution leaves theory with very little to say.
By placing all but the most completely empty and formal properties of
action under the study of history, Mises conceded too much to the historicists.
Mises' praxeology has less to say about human action than we might have
hoped. Most of what we are
accustomed to view as theory becomes history.
Mises a priorism was cogently criticized by Hayek (1937).
The theorems of catallactics all entail assumptions about how
expectations and knowledge. Such assumptions are empirical in nature, not a
priori. But then Mises was wrong to claim that economic theory could
address such questions as what consequences price controls must have,
(1933, p. 118). Third,
Mises system leaves no room for a theory of expectations.
In Mises system, expectations are a matter of understanding.
Expectations, for Mises, are ideas about the future of economic life.
Thus, they are about the content of action, not its formal structure.
Acts apprehending the content of action are acts of understanding.
They fall outside the purview of pure theory, which employs only
conception. (See Koppl 1997.) Finally, Mises exaggerates the difference between a priori and a posteriori and therefore, the difference between theory and history. Any theory, any argument, has its a priori element. The general form of a theoretical argument is If A, then B. The antecedent, A, is the arguments a priori. Some elements of the a priori will have been tested, others are guesses. Still others are conventions and thus true merely on account of how we use language. Any element of this a priori can be criticized as not true or not useful. Thus the a priori is always present, but it is neither inviolable nor immune from criticism. (See Machlup 1978 on the difference between psychologically and logically apriori and on other issues.) If Popper was right to claim that science progresses by conjectures and refutations, then the a priori element in our reasoning may change over time in the wake of experience. Similarly, the difference between theory and history or pure and applied theory is a matter of degree. III. SCHUTZ AND HAYEK Hayek and Schutz both attempted to reform Misess methodology. Hayek adopted a naturalistic attitude. Schutz adopted a phenomenological perspective. Both, however, remained Misesians. Both defended, in some way, apriorism, methodological dualism, methodological individualism, understanding, and nomological theory. Both defended, in other words, the fundamentals of Mises methodology. Because of the differences in the foundations each thinker gave to his system, their methodologies seem quite far apart. As we shall see, they are not. Both Hayek and Schutz replaced Mises account of understanding with different account. Schutz relied on Husserls phenomenological psychology. Hayek relied on his own innovative theory of mind, based on evolutionary biology. In both cases, however, the essence of the matter is replacing Mises Bergsonian account of inter-subjective understanding with another account. And in both cases, the replacement produced a system free of the limits of Mises original position. Considering the differences in each thinkers replacement strategy (as we might call it) it is surprising to find that the two systems are compatible and may be fitted together with little modification to either system. A. SCHUTZ Schutz is famous for his synthesis of Husserl and Weber. But as Christopher Prendergast notes, Schutz did not engage in some abstract and unmotivated attempt to synthesize Weber and Husserl (1986 p. 1). Schutz motive was to shore up the methodological defenses of the Austrian school of economics. Prendergast describes Schutz as committed to overall methodological standpoint of the Austrian school (p. 3). The titular head of the school was Ludwig von Mises (p.6). The seminar Mises ran from his office in the Austrian Chamber of Commerce was the prime vehicle for forging and maintaining the distinctive theoretical, philosophical, and policy tradition of Austrian marginalism (p. 6). The Mises Circle was the main element of the inner circle of Schutzs audience (p. 5). Schutz thought that Mises methodology lacked a satisfactory theory of intersubjective understanding (Prendergast 1986, p. 11).[7] Schutz replaced Mises Bergsonian theory of inter-subjective understanding with one based on Edmund Husserls philosophy of phenomenology. This replacement allowed Schutz to rehabilitate Webers ideal type methodology. As we have seen, Mises accepted Webers methodology of ideal types with regard to history. He also accepted Bergsons theory of inter-subjective understanding. If Bergson were rejected, Schutz would need to either accept Webers theory of inter-subjective understanding or find another one. Webers theory was unsuitable because it was not very clear. Weber had claimed that the actor attaches meaning to his act. Schutz could not accept this formulation (1932a, p. 215). Moreover many of Webers most important concepts and distinctions were inadequately developed (Schutz 1932a, p. xxxi). They could not be accepted as is. Webers interpretive sociology needed rehabilitation based on a closer analysis of basic concepts, especially meaning. Schutzs analysis of meaning led him to the view that all thinking requires ideal types. Most thinkers reserve the term ideal type for the constructs of social scientists. Schutz employed it for both scientific and common-sense interpretations of the social world. We think in stereotypes. Our own experiences are meaningful only when we reflect on them. But to reflect on them is to apply ideal types to them.[8] The same holds for the interpretation of others. To interpret the meaning of anothers action is to apply some set of typifications to them. Schutz
used the terms type, ideal type, and typification.
One could use any of a number substitutes, including stereotype,
construct, and category. Whatever the label, all thinking entails ideal types.
Schutz makes no exception for direct experience, including direct
experience of others. To think about ones direct experience, one must pull back
from it and apply a retrospective glance to it (1932a, pp. 51-53).
Walsh and Lehnerts translation of Schutz does not include the
following very important sentence: Hence, the experience of a fellow-man in a
We-relation is, strictly speaking, also mediate: I apprehend his conscious
life by interpeting his bodily expressions as indications of subjectively
meaningful processes (Schutz, 1932b, p. 26).[9]
This sentence gives direct expression to Schutzs repudiation of Mises
Bergsonian theory of inter-personal interpretation.
While Schutz retained much from Bergson, including his analysis of durée,
he rejected the idea the we can enter into the lifestream of another.
He thus rejected the basic idea in Mises account of inter-subjective
understanding. This repudiation of Bergsonian intuition applies equally to common sense and scientific interpretations of human action. A further consideration applies to social science. Because social science requires complete clarity of its concepts, the experience upon which it relies is always indirect. We can draw no scientific implications from our direct experience of another. Science "nowhere refers back to the face-to-face experience" (1932, p. 223). No immediate intuitions enter science.[10] Some of Schutzs language might seem to suggest more immediacy of understanding than Schutz in fact allowed. He says, for instance, that whereas I can observe my own lived experiences only after they are over and done with, I can observe yours as they actually take place (1932, p. 102). This sounds close to the sort of entering into that Bergson and Mises argued for. But Schutz develops and qualifies the point at length (pp. 102-107). In the end he concludes that [t]he very postulate of the comprehension of the intended meaning of the other persons lived experiences becomes unfulfillable (p. 107). When we interpret the meaning of anothers action, we impute some meaning to it. We classify the action according to some set of ideal types.
This view of interpretation exposes an important ambiguity in the idea of
the meaning of anothers action. I
may interpret an action in a way that makes little or no reference to the
meaning the actor himself may have intended.
If I say that you have opened the door, I may not mean to imply that you
tried to do so. Perhaps you foot
brushes against it by chance. On
the other hand, I might interpret an action in a way that makes direct reference
to the inner experiences of the actor. The
criminal is re-enacting, say, the abuses he suffered as a child.
There is a kind of inner meaning and an outer meaning.
This is the difference between the objective and the
subjective meaning of an act. Subjective meaning refers to the mental processes of the actor.[11] The subjective meaning tells us what went on in the actors mind to produce the action. The objective meaning is the meaning as it exists independently of the thought processes of the actor.[12] Objective meaning therefore consists only in a meaning-context within the mind of the interpreter, whereas subjective meaning refers beyond it to a meaning-context in the mind of the producer (Schutz, 1932, p. 134). Schutz illustrates with the concept of wood is being cut (p. 110). That wood is being cut may mean the ax slicing the tree and the wood splitting into bits. That would be an objective meaning. On the other hand there is genuine understanding of the other person (p. 111) in which the center of attention is the woodcutters own lived experiences as actor (p. 110). We might ask what the cutters project is and why he has chosen it. The difference between objective and subjective meanings, however, is only one of degree. Between the extreme poles of the most private subjective meaning and pure objective meaning there is a whole series of intermediate steps (p. 136). Any interpretation of the actions of others contains some reference to the meaning the actor intended. Some interpretations, however, provide more detailed account of subjective meaning than others. Thus we can rank (personal) ideal types according to the completeness of the description of the actors subjective meaning context. When we fill in only a few particulars, the ideal type is anonymous. When we fill in many particulars, the ideal type is concrete. We might say that the ideal type has a psychological programming. Anonymous types have very little psychological programming. Concrete (or intimate) types have a rich psychological programming. This programming, however, refers to subjective meaning contexts. It does not refer to particular actions the type might perform.[13] The social world is arrayed about me as a network of ideal types. Those closest to me include the ideal types of greatest intimacy. Those farther away are more anonymous. My ideal types of my loved ones are filled in with many particulars. Those of my colleagues are highly concrete, but less intimate than those of my family. My ideal types of say, my fellow voters, are rather anonymous, though I do imagine some subjective meaning context for their choices. Finally, at the highest level of anonymity is my ideal type of acting man as such, the fellow human who acts.[14] All that
has been said of the ideal types of common sense may be applied to scientific
ideal types as well. In particular,
the interpretive sociologist uses ideal types of varying degrees of anonymity.
What we call either history or applied economics entails the
use of relatively concrete ideal types. Theory
uses more anonymous types. The
distinction, therefore, between theory and history is not the categorical one
Mises imagined. We use the term
theory for arguments and explanations that use only relatively anonymous
types; we use the terms history and applied theory when relatively
concrete types are used. Where one
draws the line between theory and history is largely a matter of
taste. Schutz's
system has the five characteristics of Mises' system listed earlier.
First, it is aprioristic. The
knowledge of social science is based "on conclusions of thought,"
Schutz maintained. "The
original and fundamental scheme of science, the expressive scheme of its
propositions, and the interpretive scheme of its explanations is, therefore,
essentially that of formal logic" (1932, p. 223). Second,
Schutz was a methodological dualist. The
methods of the social sciences differ from those of the natural sciences.
The social refer to subjective meaning, the natural sciences do not. The methods of phenomenological psychology, therefore, apply
only in social science. Third,
Schutz defended "understanding."
Indeed, The Phenomenology of the
Social World is a detailed account of what inter-subjective understanding is
(phenomenologically). Fourth,
Schutz defended methodological individualism.
Interpretive sociology, for Schutz, attempts "to explain human
actions" by asking "what model of an individual mind can be
constructed" to "explain the observed facts" (Schutz 1953 p. 43). Fifth,
Schutz defended nomological theory. Schutz
considers the "obvious objection" that "the existence of the
so-called law-constructing (or nomothetic) social sciences contradicts our
earlier assertion that all social sciences are type-constructing in nature"
(1932, p. 242). He reproduces two lengthy passages of Mises `Soziologie
und Geschichte,' an essay that we have already quoted repeatedly
(1932 pp. 242-243). In them,
Mises criticizes Weber's ideal type methodology for failing to recognize that
the fundamental laws of economics "are valid always and everywhere when the
conditions presupposed by them are present" (Mises as quoted in Schutz,
1932, p. 243).[15]
"No doubt Mises' criticism is valid against Weber's earliest formulations
of the concept of ideal type" (p. 243).
But the concept as rehabilitated by Schutz is immune to Mises criticism. In particular, Schutz's concept permits both
"empirical" and "eidetic" ideal types, "and by eidetic
we mean `derived from essential insight'" (1932, p. 244).
With
Schutz's enlarged sense of ideal type, "even the examples cited by Mises --
the economic principle, the basic laws of price formation, and so forth -- are
in our sense ideal types" (1932, p. 244). Thus, we can accept Mises' criticism of Weber while
maintaining that economic theory uses "ideal types" in the Schutzian
sense. "Mises' argument really
turns out to be a defense against the intrusion of ideal types of too great
concreteness and too little anonymity into economics" (p. 244). Economic theory uses only highly anonymous ideal types,
"and it is in this sense that economic principles are, in Mises' words,
`not a statement of what usually happens, but of what necessarily must
happen'" (p. 245). Thus,
economics is, for Schutz, "nomothetic." Schutz's
rehabilitation of Mises' position was successful in the sense that it is free of
the deficiencies of Mises' system I listed earlier.
First, I cited Mises' use of the Bergosn's concept of intuition.
Schutz, as we have seen, rejected Bergsonian intution. Second, I
noted that Mises' distinction between theory and history leaves
"theory" with very little to say about human action.
Mises claim that economics can predict such things as "what
consequences price controls must have" (1933, p. 118) is inconsistent with
his claim that "praxeology" describes only the form of action and not
its content. In the language of
Schutz, we may now say that in Mises' methodology, only the most completely
anonymous ideal types are admitted in economic theory.
But the sorts of predictions Mises thought economics to give require
ideal types that are not completely anonymous.
They are highly anonymous, but not perfectly anonymous.
With Schutz we can and should admit such imperfectly anonymous types into
economic theory.
Third, I noted that Mises methodology makes a theory of expectations
impossible. As I have argued on
another occasion, Schutz concept of anonymity "lays the ground for a
subjectivist theory of expectations" (1997, p. 73). Economic actors cannot
reliably predict the actions of relatively concrete ideal types.
But if certain identifiable conditions prevail, economic actors can
reliably predict the actions of anonymous types. The economist, therefore, can reliably predict the
expectations of economic actors when he can imagine them to be themselves
relying upon anonymous types in the formation of those expectations.[16] Finally,
I noted that Mises exaggerates the difference between a priori and a posteriori
and, therefore, the difference between theory and history.
Schutz, as we have seen, recognized the movement from theory to history
as a continuous one. Schutz's system gives us a Misesian methodology free of the defects characteristic of Mises' original system. The concept of anonymity is only one of many important contributions Schutz made to Misesian methodology B. HAYEK Hayek
published two books in 1952, The Counter Revolution of Science and The Sensory Order. These two books are closely related.
Their arguments should be viewed as continuous and interdependent.
The former reprints essays published in the 1940's. The latter brings to fruition a position Hayek developed in
an unpublished essay from 1920. Together
they map out a system of thought which entails a perfectly Misesian methodology
of the social sciences.[17]
The Counter Revolution of Science
begins with a brief look at "The Influence of the Natural Sciences on the
Social Sciences." This short
chapter is followed by a longer chapter on "The Problem and the Method of
the Natural Sciences." This
second chapter is a kind of semi-popular treatment of many of the themes of The Sensory Order.[18] In particular, the chapter contains summary statements of
important points made in the concluding chapter of The Sensory Order, "Philosophical Consequences."
That same philosophical chapter of The
Sensory Order contains three separate references to The
Counter-Revolution of Science. Another
three references appear earlier in the book. The
Counter-Revolution of Science is the only work of Hayek cited in The
Sensory Order. It seems fair to
conclude that the two books are developing one continuous argument.
Logically, The Sensory Order is volume one; The Counter Revolution of Science is volume two.[19] It is
very significant, I think, that Hayek starts The Counter Revolution of Science where The Sensory Order leaves off.
Hayek saw humanity as being, in a sense, located between the extremes
explored by natural and social science. The
natural sciences move "down" from large observable phenomena to small
causes that we can observe only indirectly.
The social sciences move "up" from small observable causes to
large (unintended) consequences we can observe only indirectly. Early in The
Counter Revolution of Science Hayek explains that it is the procedure of
natural science "to substitute for the classification of events which our
senses provide a new one which groups together not what appears alike but what
proves to behave in the same manner in similar circumstances" (p. 31).
He notes that this view "may sound surprising" (31).
Indeed, at the time this was written philosophers (including positivists)
tended to argue that natural science simply re-orders our sensory data.
Who seriously argued that the sensory order was displaced
by science? The answer, not
surprisingly, is Hayek. In the
concluding, philosophical chapter of The
Sensory Order, Hayek says natural science consists in the
"reclassification, or breaking up of the classes formed by the implicit
relations which manifest themselves in our discrimination of sensory qualities,
and the replacement of these classes by new classes defined by explicit
relations" (1952b. p. 169). For the
natural scientist, the "views people hold about the external world are . .
. always a stage to be overcome" (1952a, p. 39). The social scientist, Hayek argues, is in a very different
position. He must consider
"the fact that people perceive the world and each other through sensations
and concepts which are organized in a mental structure common to all of
them" (p. 39). He must
recognize "the fact that man has a definite picture, and that the picture
of all beings whom we recognize as thinking men and whom we can understand is to
some extent alike" (39). This
fact "is a reality of great consequence" and the basis of social
science (39).
In recognizing this fact and making it the foundation of social science,
Hayek is accepting Mises' apriorism. "We
know . . . that in his conscious decisions man classifies external stimuli in a
way we know solely from our own subjective experience of this kind of
classification" (43). We
assume the identity of mental structure, we "take it for granted,"
even though "no objective test" could confirm it (43).
"It would be impossible to explain or understand human action
without making use of this knowledge" (pp. 43-44).
Hayek claims that "all propositions of pure economic theory"
fit the pattern of "a statement about the implications of certain human
attitudes toward things and as such necessarily true irrespective of time and
place" (p. 55). Hayek and
Mises adopt the same aprioristic doctrine that "the [common] structure of
men's minds . . . provides us with the knowledge . . . in terms of which we can
alone describe and explain" social phenomena (p. 58). Hayeks
apriorism, however, differs from Mises in one important respect.
Hayek thought that (almost) any statement of economic theory contains
more than the a priori component which
we have just seen him label pure economic theory.
It also contains an empirical statement such as the claim that land
is often a relatively specific factor of production.
(Thus the law of rent often applies to land.)
This empirical statement is an assertion that the conditions
postulated in an economic law prevail in a given time and place (1952a,
p. 55). Hayek then cites his 1937 paper Economics and
Knowledge. As far as I know, this aprioristic doctrine is not directly expressed in The Sensory Order. The book does describe, however, how the mind evolved. Biological evolution produced a central nervous system, which imposes a classification on external stimuli by means of the organism's responses to nervous impulses. This is no less true of humans than of other species. We have, therefore, a common mental structure, which we recognize in one another. (See Hayek 1952b. See also the summaries of this system found in Butos and Koppl, 1993 and 1997; and Koppl 1997, and 1999.) Moreover, in connection with methodological dualism (to which we shall turn presently) Hayek does say that in social science "our starting point will always have to be our direct knowledge of the different kinds of mental events, which to us must remain irreducible entities" (1952b, p. 191). Finally, Hayek notes that we use our direct (introspective) knowledge of mental events in order to understand, and in some measure even predict, the results to which mental processes will lead in certain conditions (1952b, p. 192). (I will use this quote again.) Hayek also adopts Mises' methodological dualism. In the Counter Revolution, Hayek says, "We know that people will react in the same way to external stimuli which according to all objective tests are different, and perhaps also that they will react in a completely different manner to a physically identical stimulus" (1952a, p. 43). This language parallels language of Mises that we have already quoted. Also, in Theory and History, Mises defends methodological dualism by noting that, "Identical external events result sometimes in different human responses, and different external events produce sometimes the same human response. We don't know why" (1957, p. 18). The language just quoted appears also in The Sensory Order. "[P]sychology must start from stimuli defined in physical terms and proceed to show why and how the senses classify similar physical stimuli sometimes as alike and sometimes as different, and why different physical stimuli will sometimes appear as similar and sometimes as different" (1952b, pp. 7-8). His solution to this problem represents the mind as a classificatory apparatus. Hayek argues that a classificatory apparatus must be more complex than the objects it classifies with the respect to the elements accounted for in the classification (1952b, pp. 184-188). Thus, he concludes, the mind cannot fully explain itself. The last paragraph of The Sensory Order is worth quoting in full. Our conclusion, therefore, must be that to us mind must remain forever a realm of its own which we can know only through directly experiencing it, but which we shall never be able fully to explain or to 'reduce' to something else. Even though we may know that mental events of the kind which we experience can be produced by the same forces which operate in the rest of nature, we shall never be able to say which are the particular physical events which 'correspond' to a particular mental event. (1952b, p. 194) Hayek followed Mises in accepting the doctrine of understanding. Indeed, in The Sensory Order, he explicitly defends "verstehende psychology" (p. 192). We "use our direct ('introspective') knowledge of mental events in order to 'understand,' and in some measure even to predict, the results to which mental processes will lead in certain condtions" (1952b, p. 192). Chapter three of The Counter Revolution of Science, "The Subjective Character of the Data of the Social Sciences," is devoted to the idea of inter-subjective understanding. Hayek illustrates with case of an archaeologist trying to learn if a piece of stone was a manufactured tool or a product of nature. "There is no way of deciding this but by trying to understand the working of the mind of pre-historic man, of attempting to understand how he would have made such an implement" (1952a, p. 46). In The Sensory Order, Hayek develops a kind of naturalistic theory of inter-subjective understanding as a consequence of the theory of mind that is the books purpose to explain. Biological evolution favors organisms that respond appropriately to their environments. An organism's central nervous system provides it information about its environment. The "meaning" of any complex of nervous impulses is given by the organism's patterned response to it. Those organisms whose patterned responses are more sensitive to crucial features of the external world will enjoy differential reproductive success. The features of their central nervous systems that produced such responses will tend to be passed on. Thus, over biological time, species may tend to develop central nervous systems that convey more detailed information about the environment and permit a more subtle response to it. An organism with a brain has a mind. The mind is a classificatory device that sorts complexes of nervous impulses into to equivalence classes according a hierarchical set of rules. The classes constitute the mind map of the world. They tell it what sort of a world it inhabits. The classes exist in the form of the organisms patterned responses to nervous impulses and thus (though only indirectly) to external events. As Butos and I (1997) have said, the simplest version of a central nervous system matching Hayeks description would put any impulse cluster into one of two boxes. We might think of one box as carrying the label go right and the other go left. Biological evolution would tend to select, from among such simple organisms, those whose central nervous systems tended to say go left when more nourishing environments existed to the left and go right when more nourishing environments existed to the right. Natural selection would tend to favor those spontaneous variations that generated more complex responses (go left then right) to environmental stimuli. Emergent species would, then, tend to have ever more receptor sites, ever more nerve fibers, ever larger brains, and, in consequence, ever more complex ways of classifying and responding to incoming signals The human species has overcome the biological costs of a large brain and acquired an unusually complex central nervous system that guides human action. The sensory order, which we spontaneously take to characterize the external world, really describes the classificatory apparatus of the mind. That classificatory apparatus, however, reflects some features of the external world, since it was shaped by the world over biological time. Any two humans share the same philogenic history and thus share the same basic mental structure. That structure consists in the pattered responses of the organism to the nervous impulses stimulated by the external world. But precisely because the mind is a finite classificatory apparatus, the rules governing its behavior are not explicitly knowable by it. The point
here is combinatorial. Consider a
simple classificatory apparatus. We
have, say, a machine designed to sort oranges into two boxes, large and
small. Any orange has only
one diameter. The machine, however,
recognizes two kinds of diameters, large and small.
Thus, with respect to diameter, the sorting machine is more complicated
than the oranges it sorts. More
generally, a classificatory apparatus must be more complex than the objects it
classifies with the respect to the elements accounted for in the classification.
From this
result it follows that the mind cannot fully explain itself.
To explain itself, the mind would have to classify possible mental
events. The mind would therefore
have to be more complex than itself, an absurdity.
Thus our explanations of mental events are always only of the principle
and never truly complete. The mind
cannot fully explain itself. For
this combinatorial reason, inter-subjective understanding is always a matter of
"intuitive" grasping of "meanings."
It is always a matter of "understanding."
(Hayek 1952b, 1962). Hayek
accepted Mises methodological individualism.
In The Counter-Revolution of
Science, Hayek distinguishes those of an actors opinions that guide his
actions from those which provide theories of such collectives as
capitalism and society. That
[the social scientist] consistently refrains from treating these pseudo-entities
as facts, and that he systematically starts from the concepts which guide
individuals in their actions and not from the results of their theorizing about
their actions, is the characteristic feature of that methodological
individualism which is closely connected with the subjectivism of the social
sciences (1952a, p. 64). Finally,
Hayek accepted Mises claim that economics is nomothetic.
In Hayeks work this idea is most characteristically expressed in the
formula that economics studies the unintended consequences of human action.
If social phenomena showed no order except insofar as they were
consciously designed, there would indeed be no room for theoretical sciences of
society (1952a, p. 69). The
Misesian character of The Counter
Revolution of Science is further revealed by the many references to Mises it
contains. It contains a famous
footnote in which Hayek celebrates Mises' subjectivism.
It is significant, I think, how sweeping the praise is.
Subjecivism is a development which has probably been carried out most
consistently by Ludwig von Mises, Hayek notes.
Moreover, most peculiarities of his views . . . trace to the fact that
in the consistent development of the subjectivist approach he has for a long
time moved ahead of his contemporaries.
Hayek suggests that all the characteristic features of his
theories, including what he calls his a
priorism, and his criticism of planning, follow directly from the
central thesis of subjectivism (1952a, p. 52,n.7).
The book contains several other direct references to Mises, including one
approving of Mises term praxeology (p. 45, n.3). Hayeks
rehabilitation of Mises methodology was successful in the sense that it is
free of the deficiencies of Mises system that I listed earlier.
First, I cited Mises use of Bergsons concept of intuition.
Hayek clearly rejected this theory of inter-subjective understanding in
favor of his combinatorial theory. Second, I
noted that Mises distinction between theory and history leaves theory
with very little to say about human action.
Hayeks clearest statements on this issue are to be found in his 1937
paper Economics and Knowledge.
But
as we have seen, in The Counter-Revolution
of Science he argues that the statements of economic theory contain
empirical statements to the effect that the postulated conditions of pure theory
apply in a given case. Thus, Hayek
was willing to admit such empirical content into economic theory. Third,
I noted that Mises methodology makes a theory of expectations impossible.
By admitting empirical claims into economic theory, Hayek created space
for an economic theory of expectations. Butos
and I (1993) have attempted to outline a Hayekian theory of expectations. Finally, I noted that Mises exaggerates the difference between a priori and a posteriori and, therefore, the difference between theory and history. Hayeks willingness to include empirical content into economic theory breaks down Mises exaggerated distinction between theory and history. The Sensory Order carries the philosophical implication that the distinction between a priori and a posteriori is fluid. As I noted earlier, for Hayek, the minds structure reflects some features of the external world, since it was shaped by the world. Our a priori knowledge is shpaed by experience. Thus, Hayeks theory breaks down Mises sharp distinction between a priori and a posteriori. IV. Fitting Shutz and Hayek Together Schutz and Hayek were both Misesian methodologists who rejected one unfortunate feature of Mises system, namely Bergsonian intuition. But each thinker developed Mises system in different directions. It might seem, therefore, that my proposal to integrate the two would encounter obstacles. In fact, however, no fundamental obstacles exist in the philosophy or psychology of each thinker to frustrate such a synthesis. I will look first at differences in their ideas in philosophy and then at differences in their ideas in ideas in psychology. Hayek
and Husserl did not hold compatible philosophical positions.
This would seem to doom any attempt to simply stitch together Hayek and
Schutz. Schutz was, after all, a close follower of Husserl.
Surprisingly, this difference makes no difference.
In a famous Appended Note to The
Phenomenology of the Social World, Schutz explained that he was engaged in
an exercise in phenomenological psychology, not transcendental
psychology. This means that
Schutz was specifically avoiding as many philosophical commitments as possible.
Schutzs kept his analysis of the life world relatively close to
the ground. He did not commit
himself to any of Husserls metaphysical doctrines, nor to Husserls claim
that we can ground our knowledge through transcendental phenomenology. It means, importantly, that Schutz never left the
naturalistic attitude of common sense. He
takes the existence of the life world and of his fellow humanity as
unproblematic. Hayeks
points of disagreement with phenomenological philosophy all concern
transcendental phenomenology. Hayek was an anti-foundationalist, anti-rationalist, and
anti-Cartesian. He could not
accept, therefore, Husserls attempt to ground all knowledge in a Cartesian
meditation. But none of this speaks
to the empirical accuracy of Schutzs analysis of the life world. There are no basic philosophical obstacles to integrating
Schutz and Hayek. Hayek and Schutz have consistent psychological theories. Recently, Langlois (1998) has argued that Schutzs psychology employs a variant of the categorization-action system. The same may be said of Hayek. In each case, action is explained as a patterned response to a situation which the agent must define and respond to. In Hayeks case, such categorization is viewed externally and from, ultimately, an evolutionary perspective. With Schutz the categorization is viewed from within and described phenomenologically. Hayek looks from the outside. Schutz looks from the inside. Both are looking at the same object: the agents definition of the situation. Hayeks account of attention in The Sensory Order, for instance, is very similar to Schutzs account of the system of relevancies that guides action. In psychology, too, there are no basic obstacles to integrating Schutz and Hayek. V. Does it matter? The
attempt to integrate Schutz and Shackle will not be worth the effort unless it
brings some fruit. I believe there
are benefits to it. My co-authors
and I have outlined an integration of Schutzian and Hayekian perspectives on
expectations. (See especially,
Koppl 1998. See also Butos and
Koppl, 1993; Koppl and Langlois, 1994; Koppl, 1997).
As we have seen, one of the deficiencies of Mises system was its
inability to incorporate a theory of expectations.
Neither Schutz nor Hayek can said to have a theory of expectations, I
believe. But both contain much
suggestive material. The
theory of expectations my co-authors and I have outlined seems to have empirical
implications. The theory of Big
Players builds on this theory of expectations.
The theory of Big Players explains, in effect, how important
non-anonymous ideal types may corrupt order in markets.
Important insights from Hayek are needed, however, to complete the theory
and draw out its empirical implications. The
theory seems to hold up empirically (Koppl and Yeager 1996; Ahmed, et al., 1997;
Broussard and Koppl 1999; Koppl and Nardone, 1997; Koppl and Mramor 1998; and
Beckett and Koppl 1998). Moreover,
the theory has rather direct policy implications.
Thus, there is at least one example of a research program sustained by
the integration of Schutz and Hayek. I
conjecture that there are many ways to apply an integration of Schutz and Hayek.
The theory of the firm is a prominent example.
The work of Richard Langlois has drawn heavily on both Hayek and Schutz.
It has also advanced the capabilities theory of the firm.
(Langlois 1998 is especially suggestive.)
Law and
economics is another field in which one might hope for a benefit from
integrating Schutz and Hayek. Hayeks
work on law is famous. But Schutz,
too gave serious thought to law. The
famous legal scholar Hans Kelsen was one of his teachers. The final chapter of The
Phenomenology of the Social World contains a fairly lengthy discussion of
law and of Kelsen. The concepts of
stability and efficiency of rules might be clarified by arguments
drawing on both Schutz and Hayek. Finance is a large field for the application of Schutzian and Hayekian ideas. (I have already cited my own efforts in this area.) The current vogue for GARCH models is but one small example of an area where an integrated subjectivist perspective might contribute to the debate (Broussard and Koppl 1999). Many other examples exist. The proof of the pudding, however, is in the eating. It is thus necessary that Austrian economists go beyond programmatic statements of the relation of Schutz and Hayek. We must go out and apply our programmatics to real problems. BIBLIOGRAPHY Ahmed Ehsan, Roger Koppl, J.Barkley Rosser, and Mark V. White. 1997. "Complex Bubble Persistence in Closed-End Country Funds," Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 32(1): 19-37. Beckett, Catherine and Roger Koppl. 1998. "Big Players and Money Demand," manuscript, Fairleigh Dickinson University. Bergson, Henri. [1903] 1946. Introduction to Metaphysics, in Bergson, Henri, The Creative Mind: An Introduction to Metaphysics, translated by Mabelle L. Andison, New York: Wisdom Library. Broussard, John and Roger Koppl. 1999. "Big Players and the Russian Ruble: Explaining Volatility Dynamics," Managerial Finance, forthcoming. Butos, William and Roger Koppl. 1993. "Hayekian Expectations: Theory and Empirical Applications," Constitutional Political Economy, 4(3): 303-329. Butos, William and Roger Koppl. 1997. "The Varieties of Subjectivism: Keynes and Hayek on Expectations." History of Political Economy, 29(2): 327-359. Caldwell, Bruce. 1984. Praxeology and its Critics: An Appraisal, History of Political Economy, 16: 363-379. Cosmides, Leda and John Tooby. 1992. Cognitive Adaptations for Social Exchange, in Barkow, Jerome H., Leda Cosmides, and John Tooby edited The Adapted Mind: Evolutionary Psychology and the Generation of Culture, New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press. Hayek, F.A. [1952a] 1979, The Counter-Revolution of Science: Studies on the Abuse of Reason. Indianapolis, Indiana: Liberty Press. Hayek, F. A. 1952b. The Sensory Order: An Inquiry into the Foundations of Theoretical Psychology. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. Hayek, F.A. [1963] 1967. Rules, Perception and Intelligibility, in his Studies in Philosophy, Politics and Economics, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. Helling, Ingeborg. 1984. Alfred Schutz and Felix Kaufmann: Sociology between Science and Interpretation, Human Studies 7: 141-162. Husserl, Edmund. [1911] 1965. Philosophy as Rigorous Science, in Husserl, Edmund, Phenomenology and the Crisis of Philosophy, translated and edited by Quentin Lauer, New York: Harper Torchbooks. Koppl, Roger. 1999. "Apriorism and Dualism," Advances in Austrian Economics, forthcoming. Koppl, Roger. 1998. "Lachmann on the Subjectivism of Active Minds," in Koppl and Mongiovi edited, Subjectivism and Economic Analysis: Essays in Memory of Ludwig M. Lachmann, London and New York: Routledge. Koppl, Roger. 1997. "Mises and Schutz on Ideal Types." Cultural Dynamics, 1997, 9(1): 67-76. Koppl, Roger. 1996. "It is High Time we take our Ignorance more Seriously," International Review of Financial Analysis, 5(3): 259-72. Koppl, Roger and Dusan Mramor. 1998. "Big Players in Slovenia," manuscript, Fairleigh Dickinson University. Koppl, Roger and Carlo Nardone. 1997. "The Angular Distribution of Asset Returns in Delay Space," manuscript, Fairleigh Dickinson University. Koppl, Roger and Leland Yeager. 1996. "Big Players and Herding in Asset Markets: The Case of the Russian Ruble," Explorations in Economic History, 33(3): 367-83. Lachmann, Ludwig. 1981. Forward to Ludwig von Mises, Epistemological Problems of Economics, translated by George Reisman, New York and London: New York University Press. Langlois, Richard N. 1998. "Rule-following, Expertise, and Rationality: a New Behavioral Economics?" in Kenneth Dennis, ed., Rationality in Economics:Alternative Perspectives. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers Langlois, Richard N. 1989. What Was Wrong with the 'Old' Institutional Economics? (And What Is Still Wrong with the 'New'?)" Review of Political Economy 1(3): 272-300. Langlois, Richard N. and Roger Koppl. 1991. "Fritz Machlup and Marginalism: A Reevaluation," Methodus, 3(2): 86-102. Lavoie, Don. 1994. The Interpretive Turn, in Boettke, Peter J. edited, The Elgar Companion to Austrian Economics, Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar. Machlup, Fritz. 1978. Methodology of Economics and Other Social Sciences, New York: Academic Press. McGrew, W. C. and Anna T. C. Feistner. 1992. Two Nonhuman Primate Models for the Evolution of Human Food Sharing: Chimpanzees and Callitrichids, in Barkow, Jerome H., Leda Cosmides, and John Tooby edited The Adapted Mind: Evolutionary Psychology and the Generation of Culture, New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press. Mises, Ludwig, [1933] 1981. Epistemological Problems of Economics, translated by George Reisman, New York and London: New York University Press. Mises, Ludwig. [1957] 1969. Theory and History: An Interpretation of Social and Economic Evolution, Westport, Connecticut: Arlington House Publishers. Mises, Ludwig. 1966. Human Action: A Treatise on Economics, third revised edition, Chicago: Henry Regnery Company. Natanson, Maurice. 1973. Edmund Husserl: Philosopher of Infinite Tasks, Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press. ODriscoll, Gerald and Mario Rizzo. 1985. The Economics of Time and Ignorance, Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Prendergast, Christopher. 1986. Alfred Schutz and the Austrian School of Economics, American Journal of Sociology, 92(1): 1-26. Schutz, Alfred. [1932a] 1967. The Phenomenology of the Social World, translated by George Walsh and Frederick Lehnert, Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press. Schutz, Alfred. [1932b] 1976. The Dimensions of the Social World, in Schutz, Alfred, Collected Papers II: Studies in Social Theory, edited by Arvid Brodersen, The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. Schutz, Alfred. [1953] 1962. in Schutz, Alfred, Collected Papers I: The Problem of Social Reality, edited by Maurice Natanson, The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
Roger
Koppl Paper delivered to the Workshop on Spontaneous Orders: Austrian Economics, Philosophy, and Aesthetics sponsored byCenter for Interdisciplinary Business Research in Economics and Organization Copenhagen School of Business Department of Comparative Literature of the University of Copenhagen 3 November 1998 * Many conversations with Peter Boettke have helped me in developing the ideas of this paper. In particular, I have finally come to agree with his claim that Hayek is a Misesian. Peter is not responsible for any errors the paper may contain. [1] Husserl claimed that all natural science, including psychology, is naïve because it assumes uncritically that a natural world exists (1911, p. 85). In this sense, Hayeks naturalistic psychology is probably not naïve. [2] A more complete treatment would address Schutzs notion of relevancy and Hayeks related notion of attention. It would also discuss each authors treatment of the division of knowledge in society. [3] As far as I know, ODriscoll and Rizzo (1985) were the first authors to recognize the importance of Bergson to Mises thought. [4] Concepts such as purpose and preference have application, however, in behavioral biology. Even the concept of voluntary exchange applies as in the case of vampire bats (Cosmides and Tooby, 1992 and McGrew and Feistner 1992). Thus, methodological dualism may be a matter of degree just as the distinction between theory and history is a matter of degree. [5] Don Lavoie greatly advanced Misesian interpretation by pointing out the fundamental identity between vital aspects of Mises position and the views of Dilthey and other German historicists. See Lavoie 1994. [6] Mises treatment of methodological individualism is more sophisticated in Human Action than in Epistemological Problems of Economics. [7] Predergast says Schutz was also criticizing Mises and Menger for adopting the Aristotelian view that there are in social life real essences knowable by pure or categorical intuition (p. 12). Schutz followed Felix Kaufmann in seeing basic terms such as marginal utility as defining the field of inquiry. It is clearly correct to contrast Schutz and Menger on this point. But on this point there is no contrast between Schutz and Mises. In Sociology and History, which Schutz cites in The Phenomenology of the Social World, Mises cites Kaufmann and takes up Kaufmanns position on the matter. [8] We attend to our experiences with a retrospective glance. By attending to it, we become conscious of it. This is the importance of Franz Brentanos concept of the intentionality of consciousness for Schutz system. Brentano taught that all consciousness is consciousness of something. An ideal type describes the something of which we are conscious when we are conscious of something. Husserl was Brentanos student (Natanson, 1973, p. xiii). Husserl followed Brentanos doctrine of intentionality. As a phenomenologist, Schutz was obliged to follow it as well. Thus, my statement that we apply an ideal type is metaphorical. [9] Schutz 1932b was translated by Thomas Luckmann. [10] Social science is "never" based on "prepredicative Acts of laying hold on" (1932, p. 223). [11] We speak, then, of the subjective meaning of the product if we have in view the meaning-context within which the product stands or stood in the mind of the producer. To know the subjective meaning of the product means that we are able to run over in our own minds in simultaneity or quasi-simultaneity the polythetic Acts which constituted the experience of the producer (Schutz, 1932, p. 133). [12] Objective meaning, on the contrary, we can predicate only of the product as such, that is, of the already constituted meaning-context of the thing produced, whose actual production we meanwhile disregard (Schutz, 1932, pp. 133-134). [13] Behavioralists have sometimes endowed the same ideal type with lots of programming of the second type but little programming of the first type. They have, in other words, imagined relatively anonymous ideal types to be programmed (in our second sense) to perform relatively specific tasks. See Machlup 1978, p. 397n.) [14] My goals for the current paper do not permit me discuss Schutzs treatment of the problem of relevance and the related problem of the division of knowledge in society. It is worth noting, however, that Mises, Schutz, and Hayek shared the theme of the division of knowledge in society. [15] The quote from Mises can be found in Mises 1933, p. 85. [16] The theory of expectations I briefly adumbrate in the text is developed more carefully in Butos and Koppl, 1993; and in Koppl 1996,1997, and 1998. Applications of the theory are made in Koppl and Yeager 1996; Ahmed, et al., 1997; Broussard and Koppl 1999; Koppl and Nardone, 1997; Koppl and Mramor 1998; and Beckett and Koppl 1998. [17] As I have indicated on another occasion (Koppl, 1999), I think Hutchison's distinction between Hayek I and Hayek II is, at best, greatly exaggerated. [18] The footnotes on pages 36 and 37 are particularly revealing. [19] William Butos first drew my attention to the close connection between these two books. |